The Boy or Girl Paradox: Two Variants
This classic paradox explores how subtly different phrasing in probability problems can lead to distinct outcomes. We’ll examine two versions involving two-child families.
Part A: “At Least One Son”
Given: Ms. Jackson has two children. You are told that at least one is a boy.
Question: What is the probability that both children are boys?
Analysis
There are four equally likely combinations of two children:
- Boy–Boy (BB)
- Boy–Girl (BG)
- Girl–Boy (GB)
- Girl–Girl (GG)
The “at least one is a boy” condition eliminates GG, leaving:
- BB
- BG
- GB
These remaining cases are equally likely, so:
- Only 1 out of 3 has both children as boys.
Answer:
\[ P(\text{both are boys} \mid \text{at least one is a boy}) = \boxed{\frac{1}{3}} \]
Part B: “You See a Boy”
Given: Ms. Parker has two children, and you see one of them, a boy.
Question: What is the probability that both children are boys?
Analysis
This is a subtler form of conditioning. You’re not told abstractly that “at least one is a boy.” Instead, you directly observe a boy—without knowing if he’s the older or younger child.
Each family combination (BB, BG, GB, GG) is equally likely to begin with. Now consider the chance that you see a boy under each scenario:
- BB: Seeing a boy is guaranteed (either child is a boy).
- BG: 50% chance (you might see the boy or the girl).
- GB: 50% chance.
- GG: 0% chance (no boys to see).
Weight the likelihoods based on visibility:
- BB: 1
- BG: 0.5
- GB: 0.5
- GG: 0
Normalize:
- Total weight: \( 1 + 0.5 + 0.5 = 2 \)
- BB has weight 1 out of 2.
Answer:
\[ P(\text{both are boys} \mid \text{you see a boy}) = \boxed{\frac{1}{2}} \]
Conclusion
These two problems differ in how the information is obtained:
- Part A conditions on a fact about the family.
- Part B conditions on a specific observation.
This small shift leads to very different probabilities: \( \frac{1}{3} \) versus \( \frac{1}{2} \).